Aristotle or Plato Term Paper

Total Length: 3303 words ( 11 double-spaced pages)

Total Sources: 1+

Page 1 of 11

Plato's Theory Of The Tripartite Soul

The Republic is an influential dialogue by Plato, written in the first half of the 4th century BC. This Socratic dialogue mainly concerns political philosophy and ethics. The political ideas are clarified by picturing a utopia. The Republic also contains the famous allegory of the cave, with which Plato clarifies his theory of ideal forms. The Republic, which is the standard English translation of the title, is somewhat of a misnomer, as the government theorized by Plato resembles an authoritarian aristocracy. Nonetheless, the work is generally recognized a foundational text in political philosophy. The scene of the dialogue is the house of Cephalus at Piraeus, a city beyond the walls of ancient Athens. It was the port of entry and exit for trade into Athens. Socrates was not known to venture outside of Athens regularly. Socrates narrates the whole dialogue the day after it actually took place, to Timaeus, Hermocrates, and Critias, among others.

Plato's philosophy went through a number of stages. As a pupil of Socrates, he began as an analytical and possibly skeptical philosopher. However, throughout his life Eastern philosophy and its representatives at Athens, the Pythagoreans, increasingly influenced him and this took him towards mysticism, and towards number mysticism in particular. A number of recurring themes can be seen in Plato's work: (1) a belief in the immortality of the soul; (2) a rejection of empiricism, represented in Athenian culture at the time by the Sophists; (3) hostility towards the body and sense experience and a belief that virtuous living depends on reason; (4) an attempt to discover the purpose of existence, both for man as an individual and for the world as a whole; (5) a defense of the aristocratic form of government.

In the Republic, Plato puts forward the doctrine of the tripartite soul. The soul, which is originally not connected with a body, has three parts, each corresponding to a certain style of living and psychological orientation. He used the image of a charioteer and two horses to illustrate this. The charioteer represents reason. The better of the two horses is allied to "spirit" which here does not denote another name for the soul, but rather refers to that style of life, which is orientated towards the pursuit of fame and honor, particularly in battle. The bad horse is associated with appetite, instinct and desire. The presence of "spirit" complicates and obscures the basic dualism in this scheme. It is included because it was traditional in Greek society to admire martial valor, but Plato has placed the life of reason above this. The dualism is a dualism of reason against appetite and to live a good life is to reject appetite, instinct and desire and the temptation of physical things in favor of reason and the contemplative life. Appetite allies itself with the body and reason with the soul, but strictly the division of appetite and reason exists in the soul and it is only by giving way to appetite that man falls into association with the body. Thus Plato advances the Pythagorean doctrine that originally man existed as a disembodied soul and became incarnate because he fell from this original state of grace. This makes Plato the originator of the philosophical doctrine of the fall of man, reflected in either a literal or allegorical fashion in Genesis.

Plato makes the comparison between the form of the city and the form of the human being. We are to imagine ourselves to be complex "cities" and the crucial question is: "who's in charge?" How well are you governing this "city," that is, your self? The first task is to see if there are comparable factors of the soul (psyche) that are analogous to the tripartite classes of the polis: Guardian Rulers, Auxiliary Guardians, and Producers. The human soul is complex rather than simple because different aspects of it desire different ends. The appetitive aspect of soul desires sensual satisfaction, for example, for food, drink and sex. The appetites seek not some specific end, for example: Sam Adams Summer Ale, but rather a generic goal: anything quench-worthy. This distinguishes the appetites from the rational soul. Socrates finds in the soul conflicting tensions: one in the direction of satisfying the appetite, the other in the direction of frustrating the appetite.

Reason is the calculating part of the soul: the rational soul. There can be found in the same person the irrational desire to drink and the rational resistance to drink because of the bad consequences of drinking.
An example would be the offer to a starving man of a cake the starving man knows to be poisoned. The persistent desire on the part of the appetite, in contrast to the rational part which resists it at all costs, shows the separation of these aspects of the psyche. Finally, the fact that anger sometimes makes war against the appetites reveals the third part of the tripartite soul: the spirited soul (anger, assertion, aggression).

The nature of the mental processes has been an issue of central importance ever since man started to study the human mind. Plato made the first systematic effort. One of his major philosophical models, the tripartite structure of the soul, was not only a pioneering effort, it has influenced virtually every thinker interested in the human mind ever since. It still exerts a powerful influence on the organization of theory and research in present-day psychology. In this, psychology seems to share the fate of Western philosophy. The eminent philosopher A.N. Whitehead is quoted as follows: "The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato."

Popper notes: "Plato's structure of the soul is characterized by an unstable equilibrium - indeed a schism -between its upper functions, reason and will, and its lower functions, the instincts or appetites."

In Book IV of the Republic, Socrates provides a definition of justice. This definition bears strong resemblance to the two definitions of justice put forward in Book I. Cephalus ventured that justice was the honoring of legal obligations, while his son Polemarchus suggested that justice amounts to helping one's friends and harming one's enemies. These two definitions are linked by the imperative of rendering what is due, or giving to each what is appropriate. This same imperative finds variant expression in Plato's definition of justice as a political arrangement in which each person plays the appropriate role. What is due to each person is rendered all at once. Each is assigned the role in society that best suits their nature and that best serves society as a whole. In one sense, Polemarchus and Cephalus were not that far off the mark. However, in following the traditional notions, they were thinking about justice as a set of actions, rather than as a structure to society, a phenomenon that spreads out over a city as a whole.

In addition to the definition of justice, we also get the definitions of four other virtues in this section. The city's courage, Socrates tells us, is located in the auxiliaries, because it is only their courage that will affect the city as a whole. Yet right after making this claim, he goes on to tell us that what the auxiliaries possess is not simply courage but something he calls "civic courage." Many scholars have interpreted civic courage as a kind of second-rate courage. What the auxiliaries have, Socrates tells us, is the right beliefs about what is to be feared and what is not to be feared. Their courage is founded upon belief, rather than knowledge. Later in the book, he indicates that real virtue must be founded upon knowledge, suggesting that virtue based on habit or belief and not knowledge will fail when the going gets very tough. Since only the guardians possess knowledge, only the guardians can be truly virtuous or courageous.

Now that Socrates has identified societal justice, he turns to look for individual justice. Justice in the individual, as in the city, involves the correct power relationship among parts, with each part occupying its appropriate role. In the individual, the "parts" are not classes of society; instead, they are aspects of the soul, or sources of desire.

In order to make the case that individual justice parallels political justice, Socrates must claim that there are precisely three parts of the soul. By cataloging the various human desires, he identifies a rational part of the soul that lusts after truth, a spirited part of the soul that lusts after honor, and an appetitive part of the soul that lusts after everything else, including food, drink, sex, and especially money. These three parts of the soul correspond to the three classes in the just city. The appetite, or money-loving part, is the aspect of the soul most prominent among the producing class; the spirit or honor-loving part is most prominent among the auxiliaries; and reason, or the knowledge-loving part, is dominant in the guardians.

So,….....

Show More ⇣


     Open the full completed essay and source list


OR

     Order a one-of-a-kind custom essay on this topic


sample essay writing service

Cite This Resource:

Latest APA Format (6th edition)

Copy Reference
"Aristotle Or Plato" (2005, July 14) Retrieved May 3, 2024, from
https://www.aceyourpaper.com/essays/aristotle-plato-66729

Latest MLA Format (8th edition)

Copy Reference
"Aristotle Or Plato" 14 July 2005. Web.3 May. 2024. <
https://www.aceyourpaper.com/essays/aristotle-plato-66729>

Latest Chicago Format (16th edition)

Copy Reference
"Aristotle Or Plato", 14 July 2005, Accessed.3 May. 2024,
https://www.aceyourpaper.com/essays/aristotle-plato-66729