Theism and the Moral Argument Research Paper

Total Length: 3193 words ( 11 double-spaced pages)

Total Sources: 3

Page 1 of 11

Introduction

The moral argument consists of four components—moral facts, moral knowledge, moral transformation and moral rationality. As Baggett and Walls point out, the most pertinent moral facts are concerned with moral duties and values, particularly what is known as intrinsic human value.[footnoteRef:2] The question raised, of course, is where does intrinsic human value come from if not from God? Nature itself seems incapable of instilling in the human shell this universal sense of value. This is a particular fact that has to be dealt with in order to understand why the moral argument is necessarily a theistic argument, which is what this paper will argue. Moral knowledge, transformation and rationality all support the argument as well. Moral knowledge itself is a sense of the universality of morality—the the absolute validity of the platitudes of Practical Reason, as Baggett and Walls define it.[footnoteRef:3] Moral transformation refers to what Evans identifies as the relation between moral duty and personal transformation: the need for one to conform oneself and transform one’s life so that it aligns with the moral precepts that one can come to know through ascertainment of the facts of morality by using reason.[footnoteRef:4] Rationality thus plays a part in the moral argument because “rationality expunged of the relevance of morality is a thin, myopic, and emaciated notion indeed.”[footnoteRef:5] All four components work together, overlap and are integrated to form the whole of the moral argument—so much so that one cannot speak of just one component wholly without touching on the others. This paper will touch on the components while explaining and replying primarily to objections of moral knowledge, which is how one can come to theism, for knowledge of morality is a stepping stone to knowledge of God since morality itself (the objective moral order) comes from God. [2: David Baggett and Jerry Walls, God and Cosmos (Oxford University Press, 2016), 116.] [3: David Baggett and Jerry Walls, God and Cosmos (Oxford University Press, 2016), 245.] [4: Stephen Evans, God and Moral Obligation (Oxford University Press, 2013), 87.] [5: David Baggett and Jerry Walls, Good God: The Theistic Foundations of Morality (Oxford University Press, 2011), 169.]

Moral Knowledge

Moral knowledge is typically viewed as an end in and of itself by atheistic philosophers. They see moral knowledge as simply a facet of the human experience—and organizing principle for human societies, which have evolved over time and place. The basis of their argument is that one can be moral without believing in God, but of course the argument is a bit of a non-sequitur. Where faith is concerned is a different matter altogether. The issue that theist philosophers have is that morality itself cannot have come from anywhere else but God. If it is used as an organizing principle, it is used in the same way that one uses stone for building or wood for fire: these things are external to one’s self and provide one with uses. The same is true of morality. It exists in an objective sense, external to human beings, which is why they can come to universally or collectively know it, recognize it, understand it and use it—for whatever end they choose—whether as an organizing principle or as a means of personal transformation.

Justification

In order to organize or grow, one must have a sense of the moral order that exists in the world. The question behind the moral argument, however, is what one is to make of that moral order in terms of origin—i.e., where does it come from? Is it invented by man, or rather simply perceived by man, who himself created it and passes it down from generation to generation, tweaking it a bit here and there to suit himself or his society? Or does it remain objective and unchanging, calling for all to adapt themselves to it and conform to the order that it itself represents?

Naturalism will allow one to come to have moral beliefs, but it does not lead one to moral knowledge.[footnoteRef:6] In other words, the naturalist or atheist may have moral beliefs—but they are not justified by anything other than the individual’s own subjective opinion. If faith (belief) rests upon reason, where is the reason for the naturalist’s belief in morality? The naturalist may say that the reason is in the simple fact that one can discern the goodness of morality, which is reason enough to believe in it. Yet, to explore the argument it is helpful to dissect it. On what grounds is the goodness of morality based? Is it the individual himself? Does the subjective opinion of each individual determine the goodness of morality? If so, there can be no uniformity or universal morality. Morality for one may differ from one’s neighbor, and without a shared sense of morality there can be no organizing principle.

Stuck Writing Your "Theism and the Moral Argument" Research Paper?

It is in fact very much like what one perceives today in the fragmented and fractured and tribal societies of today: individuals and groups with their own senses of morality and the moral order, each defining morality according to his own beliefs. What justifies those beliefs? Simply the individual’s or group’s collective will. The will of the person or the people judges this or that action, behavior, perspective or belief to be good because it satisfies the person’s or group’s desire for goodness that aligns with his or their own viewpoint. It is justification by way of Egoism. Essentially, the morality of the naturalist and the atheist is the morality of Egoism.[footnoteRef:7] [6: David Baggett and Jerry Walls, God and Cosmos (Oxford University Press, 2016), 209.] [7: Stephen Evans, God and Moral Obligation (Oxford University Press, 2013), 72.]

The Problem of Egoism

But is Egoism sufficient philosophical justification for moral belief? It is ultimately subjective and leads to conflict and division, as every Ego stands in the way of someone else’s Ego. The philosophies of naturalism have gone out of their way in their attempt to square the circle: utilitarianism was Mill’s attempt…

[…… parts of this paper are missing, click here to view the entire document ]

…David Baggett and Jerry Walls, Good God: The Theistic Foundations of Morality (Oxford University Press, 2011), 166.]

For it cannot be denied that the prime mover is the mightiest of all—and if one is going to adhere to the argument that “might makes right,” then one must still admit that the mightiest of all is that which must be called God. This is the ontological argument of Anselm: God is that than which nothing greater can be imagined. God is the prime mover and the one Who literally “makes right” by His own might as the omnipotent being that He is.

Knowledge of Morality is Knowledge of the Will of God

Moral knowledge is knowledge of the will of God, for the moral order is the manner by which God has written his will on the world. One’s heart and mind may resist that will or accept it—one is free to choose and God is not in the business of forcing one to choose to accept. The free will that man possesses is a reflection of the freedom with which God created existence. Moral knowledge should make this clear. Those who prefer not to consent to knowledge thus stop at belief and save themselves the trouble of having to logically explain their convictions.

The reason of course is that they would prefer not to have to deal with the will of God and what that means for them in their own lives. Consenting to the will of God means consenting to transformation: it means changing oneself and becoming that which even the existentialists are always talking about when they discuss the idea of becoming. In their own language and terms, they admit to the need to become something else. They hide their justification within their own wills, thinking themselves them mightiest things they can imagine—but they are in a state of denial for it is not difficult to imagine something mightier than man. The will of God is what moral knowledge will take one to, but it is not something one will be forced to go to. God gave man the use of reason so that man could find Him. If man chooses to be led to water but does not drink, it is no one’s fault but man’s.

Conclusion

The concept of moral knowledge is such that it supports the moral argument along with the elements of facts, transformation and reason. Knowledge is that which is obtained by consenting to the facts, and it is the step that leads to transformation and faith, itself based upon reason. The moral argument thus must inevitably come down to theism. Without God, there can be no morality, for the justification required for all existence to exist is the existence of a prime mover—an eternal being that has no beginning and no end. If one is going to acknowledge an objective moral order, one must acknowledge an orderer. If one is not going to acknowledge an objective moral….....

Show More ⇣


     Open the full completed essay and source list


OR

     Order a one-of-a-kind custom essay on this topic


sample essay writing service

Cite This Resource:

Latest APA Format (6th edition)

Copy Reference
"Theism And The Moral Argument" (2019, October 10) Retrieved April 30, 2024, from
https://www.aceyourpaper.com/essays/theism-moral-argument-2174683

Latest MLA Format (8th edition)

Copy Reference
"Theism And The Moral Argument" 10 October 2019. Web.30 April. 2024. <
https://www.aceyourpaper.com/essays/theism-moral-argument-2174683>

Latest Chicago Format (16th edition)

Copy Reference
"Theism And The Moral Argument", 10 October 2019, Accessed.30 April. 2024,
https://www.aceyourpaper.com/essays/theism-moral-argument-2174683